贝壳电子书 > 英文原著电子书 > posterior analytics >

第4章

posterior analytics-第4章

小说: posterior analytics 字数: 每页4000字

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!






that is to be taken to mean that it is true of a given subject



primarily and as such。 Case (3) may be thus exemplified。 If a proof



were given that perpendiculars to the same line are parallel; it might



be supposed that lines thus perpendicular were the proper subject of



the demonstration because being parallel is true of every instance



of them。 But it is not so; for the parallelism depends not on these



angles being equal to one another because each is a right angle; but



simply on their being equal to one another。 An example of (1) would be



as follows: if isosceles were the only triangle; it would be thought



to have its angles equal to two right angles qua isosceles。 An



instance of (2) would be the law that proportionals alternate。



Alternation used to be demonstrated separately of numbers; lines;



solids; and durations; though it could have been proved of them all by



a single demonstration。 Because there was no single name to denote



that in which numbers; lengths; durations; and solids are identical;



and because they differed specifically from one another; this property



was proved of each of them separately。 To…day; however; the proof is



commensurately universal; for they do not possess this attribute qua



lines or qua numbers; but qua manifesting this generic character which



they are postulated as possessing universally。 Hence; even if one



prove of each kind of triangle that its angles are equal to two



right angles; whether by means of the same or different proofs; still;



as long as one treats separately equilateral; scalene; and



isosceles; one does not yet know; except sophistically; that



triangle has its angles equal to two right angles; nor does one yet



know that triangle has this property commensurately and universally;



even if there is no other species of triangle but these。 For one



does not know that triangle as such has this property; nor even that



'all' triangles have it…unless 'all' means 'each taken singly': if



'all' means 'as a whole class'; then; though there be none in which



one does not recognize this property; one does not know it of 'all



triangles'。



  When; then; does our knowledge fail of commensurate universality;



and when it is unqualified knowledge? If triangle be identical in



essence with equilateral; i。e。 with each or all equilaterals; then



clearly we have unqualified knowledge: if on the other hand it be not;



and the attribute belongs to equilateral qua triangle; then our



knowledge fails of commensurate universality。 'But'; it will be asked;



'does this attribute belong to the subject of which it has been



demonstrated qua triangle or qua isosceles? What is the point at which



the subject。 to which it belongs is primary? (i。e。 to what subject can



it be demonstrated as belonging commensurately and universally?)'



Clearly this point is the first term in which it is found to inhere as



the elimination of inferior differentiae proceeds。 Thus the angles



of a brazen isosceles triangle are equal to two right angles: but



eliminate brazen and isosceles and the attribute remains。 'But'…you



may say…'eliminate figure or limit; and the attribute vanishes。' True;



but figure and limit are not the first differentiae whose



elimination destroys the attribute。 'Then what is the first?' If it is



triangle; it will be in virtue of triangle that the attribute



belongs to all the other subjects of which it is predicable; and



triangle is the subject to which it can be demonstrated as belonging



commensurately and universally。







                                 6







  Demonstrative knowledge must rest on necessary basic truths; for the



object of scientific knowledge cannot be other than it is。 Now



attributes attaching essentially to their subjects attach



necessarily to them: for essential attributes are either elements in



the essential nature of their subjects; or contain their subjects as



elements in their own essential nature。 (The pairs of opposites



which the latter class includes are necessary because one member or



the other necessarily inheres。) It follows from this that premisses of



the demonstrative syllogism must be connexions essential in the



sense explained: for all attributes must inhere essentially or else be



accidental; and accidental attributes are not necessary to their



subjects。



  We must either state the case thus; or else premise that the



conclusion of demonstration is necessary and that a demonstrated



conclusion cannot be other than it is; and then infer that the



conclusion must be developed from necessary premisses。 For though



you may reason from true premisses without demonstrating; yet if



your premisses are necessary you will assuredly demonstrate…in such



necessity you have at once a distinctive character of demonstration。



That demonstration proceeds from necessary premisses is also indicated



by the fact that the objection we raise against a professed



demonstration is that a premiss of it is not a necessary truth…whether



we think it altogether devoid of necessity; or at any rate so far as



our opponent's previous argument goes。 This shows how naive it is to



suppose one's basic truths rightly chosen if one starts with a



proposition which is (1) popularly accepted and (2) true; such as



the sophists' assumption that to know is the same as to possess



knowledge。 For (1) popular acceptance or rejection is no criterion



of a basic truth; which can only be the primary law of the genus



constituting the subject matter of the demonstration; and (2) not



all truth is 'appropriate'。



  A further proof that the conclusion must be the development of



necessary premisses is as follows。 Where demonstration is possible;



one who can give no account which includes the cause has no scientific



knowledge。 If; then; we suppose a syllogism in which; though A



necessarily inheres in C; yet B; the middle term of the demonstration;



is not necessarily connected with A and C; then the man who argues



thus has no reasoned knowledge of the conclusion; since this



conclusion does not owe its necessity to the middle term; for though



the conclusion is necessary; the mediating link is a contingent



fact。 Or again; if a man is without knowledge now; though he still



retains the steps of the argument; though there is no change in



himself or in the fact and no lapse of memory on his part; then



neither had he knowledge previously。 But the mediating link; not being



necessary; may have perished in the interval; and if so; though



there be no change in him nor in the fact; and though he will still



retain the steps of the argument; yet he has not knowledge; and



therefore had not knowledge before。 Even if the link has not



actually perished but is liable to perish; this situation is



possible and might occur。 But such a condition cannot be knowledge。



  When the conclusion is necessary; the middle through which it was



proved may yet quite easily be non…necessary。 You can in fact infer



the necessary even from a non…necessary premiss; just as you can infer



the true from the not true。 On the other hand; when the middle is



necessary the conclusion must be necessary; just as true premisses



always give a true conclusion。 Thus; if A is necessarily predicated of



B and B of C; then A is necessarily predicated of C。 But when the



conclusion is nonnecessary the middle cannot be necessary either。



Thus: let A be predicated non…necessarily of C but necessarily of B;



and let B be a necessary predicate of C; then A too will be a



necessary predicate of C; which by hypothesis it is not。



  To sum

返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 2 2

你可能喜欢的